Monday, December 3, 2012

39. Incomplete Symbols



Harold R. (Hal) Foster’s Prince Valiant
© Respective copyright/trademark holders.
 (1) Descriptions. By an "incomplete " symbol we mean a symbol which is not supposed to have any meaning in isolation, but is only defined in certain contexts. In ordinary mathematics, for example,
d_   and b
dx              a
are incomplete symbols: something has to be supplied before we have anything significant. Such symbols have what may be called a "definition in use." Thus if we put

    ∇2 = 2 + 2 + 2     
           x2    y2  z2        Df,

we define the use of 2, but 2 by itself remains without meaning. This distinguishes such symbols from what (in a generalized sense) we may call proper names: "Socrates," for example, stands for a certain man, and therefore has a meaning by itself, without the need of any context. If we supply a context, as in "Socrates is mortal," these words express a fact of which Socrates himself is a constituent: there is a certain object, namely Socrates, which does have the property of mortality, and this object is a constituent of the complex fact which we assert when we say "Socrates is mortal." But in other cases, this simple analysis fails us. Suppose we say: "The round square does not exist." It seems plain that this is a true proposition, yet we cannot regard it as denying the existence of a certain object called "the round square." For if there were such an object, it would exist: we cannot first assume that there is a certain object, and then proceed to deny that there is such an object. Whenever the grammatical subject of a proposition can be supposed not to exist without rendering the proposition meaningless, it is plain that the grammatical subject is not a proper name, i.e. not a name directly representing some object. Thus in all such cases, the proposition must be capable of being so analyzed that what was the grammatical subject shall have disappeared. Thus when we say "the round square 'does not exist," we may, as a first attempt at such analysis, substitute " it is false that there is an object x which is both round and square." Generally, when "the so-and-so" is said not to exist, we have a proposition of the form*1

   "~E!(x)(φx),"

i.e.     ~{(C): φx . ≡x . x = c},

or some equivalent. Here the apparent grammatical subject (x)(φx) has completely disappeared; thus in
   "~E!(x)(φx),” (x)(φx) is an incomplete symbol.

By an extension of the above argument, it can easily be shown that (x)(φx) is always an incomplete symbol. Take, for example, the following proposition: "Scott is the author of Waverley." [Here "the author of Waverley" is (x)(x wrote Waverley).] This proposition expresses an identity; thus if "the author of Waverley" could be taken as a proper name, and supposed to stand for some object c, the proposition would be "Scott is c." But if c is anyone except Scott, this proposition is false; while if c is Scott, the proposition is "Scott is Scott," which is trivial, and plainly different from "Scott is the author of Waverley." Generalizing, we see that the proposition

     a = (x)(φx)

is one which may be true or may be false, but is never merely trivial, like a = a; whereas, if (x)(φx) were a proper name, a = (x)(φx) would necessarily be either false or the same  as the trivial proposition a = a. We may express this by saying that a = (x)(φx) is not a value of the propositional function a = y,  from which it follows that (x)(φx) is not a value of y. But since y may be anything, it follows that (x)(φx) is nothing. Hence, since in use it has meaning, it must be an incomplete symbol.

It might be suggested that "Scott is the author of Waverley" asserts that "Scott" and "the author of Waverley" are two names for the same object. But a little reflection will show that this would be a mistake. For if that were the meaning of "Scott is the author of Waverley,"what would be required for its truth would be that Scott should have been called the author of Waverley: if he had been so called, the proposition would be true, even if someone else had written Waverley; while if no one called him so, the proposition would be false, even if he had written Waverley. But in fact he was the author of Waverley at a time when no one called him so, and he would not have been the author if everyone had called him so but someone else had written Waverley. Thus the proposition "Scott is the author of Waverley "is not a proposition about names, like "Napoleon is Bonaparte"; and this illustrates the sense in which "the author of Waverley "differs from a true proper name.

Thus all phrases (other than propositions) containing the word the (in the singular) are incomplete symbols: they have a meaning in use, but not in isolation. For "the author of Waverley" cannot mean the same as "Scott," or "Scott is the author of Waverley" would mean the same as "Scott is Scott," which it plainly does not; nor can "the author of Waverley" mean anything other than "Scott," or "Scott is the author of Waverley" would be false. Hence "the author of Waverley" means nothing.

It follows from the above that we must not attempt to define "(x)(φx)," but must define the uses of this symbol, i.e. the propositions in whose symbolic expression it occurs. Now in seeking to define the uses of this symbol, it is important to observe the import of propositions in which it occurs. Take as an illustration: "The author of Waverley was a poet." This implies (1) that Waverley was written, (2) that it was written by one man, and not in collaboration, (3) that the one man who wrote it was a poet. If any one of these fails, the proposition is false. Thus "the author of 'Slawkenburgius on Noses' was a poet" is false, because no such book was ever written; "the author of 'The Maid's Tragedy' was a poet" is false, because this play was written by Beaumont and Fletcher jointly. These two possibilities of falsehood do not arise if we say "Scott was a poet." Thus our interpretation of the uses of (x)(φx) must be such as to allow for them. Now taking φx to replace "x wrote Waverley," it is plain that any statement apparently about (x)(φx)  requires (1) (x).(φx) and (2) φx . φ .x,y . x = y; here (1) states that at least one object satisfies φx, while (2) states that at most one object satisfies φx. The two together are equivalent to

     (c) : φx . ≡x . x = c,

which we defined as     E! (x)(φx).

Thus "E! (x)(φx)" must be part of what is affirmed by any proposition about (x)(φx). If our proposition is ƒ{(x)(φx)}, what is further affirmed is ƒc, if φx . ≡x . x = c. Thus we have

     ƒ{(x)(φx) . = : (C) : φx . ≡x . x = c : ƒc  Df,

i.e. "the x satisfying φx satisfies ƒx" is to mean: "There is an object c such that φx is true when, and only when, x is c, and ƒc is true, "or, more exactly: " There is a c such that 'φx' is always equivalent to 'x is c,' and ƒc." In this, " (x)(φx)" has completely disappeared; thus " (x)(φx) " is merely symbolic, and does not directly represent an object, as single small Latin letters are assumed to do*2.


*1  see post 22.

*2  We shall generally write "ƒ(x)(φx)" rather than "ƒ{(x)(φx)}" in future.

Sheldon Mayer’s Sugar and SpikeTM  © Respective copyright/trademark holders.
  This discussion of incomplete symbols, particularly those used in description, in this post and in those immediately following, shed light on some simple aspects that commonly adversely affect communication with language. Our premise stated previously in post 30, is that complexity begins with just two significant parts of speech. Our experience in life and conversation shows us that misunderstandings are very common, unfortunately almost the norm. Here we learn to spot the aspects of language that lead to misunderstanding, and by attempting to avoid making these ourselves, and carefully practicing to see them in others language it is possible to clarify problem usage kindly. This way more precise understanding may be possible.

Script: Stan Lee  Pencils and Inks: Bill Everett © Respective copyright/trademark holders.



Harold R. (Hal) Foster’s Prince Valiant
© Respective copyright/trademark holders.
 

No comments:

Post a Comment