Wednesday, February 6, 2013

49. Supplimental post Expanding #2-3



Harold R. (Hal) Foster’s Prince Valiant
© Respective copyright/trademark holders.
 
Bertrand Russell was masterful in using expressive language to make complex subject matter very clear to a careful reader. In the introductory chapters Russell uses repetition to structure the subject and impress the importance of each element introduced, and to aid in our learning. In retrospect I realize my error in condensing the earlier posts, and if the material is not clearly understood from reading them, I hope these supplemental posts are useful.



  Script:  Wm M Marston  Pencils and Inks: Harry G. Peter 
Wonder Woman™ © Respective copyright/trademark holders.
 
Assertion-sign. The sign "," called the "assertion-sign," means that what follows is asserted. It is required for distinguishing a complete proposition, which we assert, from any subordinate propositions contained in it but not asserted. In ordinary written language a sentence contained between full stops denotes an asserted proposition, and if it is false the book is in error. The sign

" prefixed to a proposition serves this same purpose in our symbolism. For example, if " (p p)" occurs, it is to be taken as a complete assertion convicting the authors of error unless the proposition "p p" is true (as it is). Also a proposition stated in symbols without this sign "" prefixed is not asserted, and is merely put forward for consideration, or as a subordinate part of an asserted proposition.

 

Inference. The process of inference is as follows: a proposition "p" is asserted, and a proposition "p implies q" is asserted, and then as a sequel the proposition "q" is asserted. The trust in inference is the belief that if the two former assertions are not in error, the final assertion is not in error. Accordingly whenever, in symbols, where p and q have of course special determinations,

" p" and " (p q)"

have occurred, then " q" will occur if it is desired to put it on record. The process of the inference cannot be reduced to symbols. Its sole record is the occurrence of " q." It is of course convenient, even at the risk of repetition, to write " p" and " (p q)" in close juxtaposition before proceeding to "q" as the result of an inference. When this is to be done, for the sake of drawing attention to the inference which is being made, we shall write instead

p q,"

which is to be considered as a mere abbreviation of the threefold statement

"p" and " (p q)" and " q."

Thus " p q" may be read "p, therefore q," being in fact the same abbreviation, essentially, as this is; for "p, therefore q" does not explicitly state, what is part of its meaning, that p implies q. An inference is the dropping of a true premise; it is the dissolution of an implication.

The use of dots. Dots on the line of the symbols have two uses, one to bracket off propositions, the other to indicate the logical product of two propositions. Dots immediately preceded or followed by "v" or "" or "≡" or "" or by "(x)," "(x,y)," "(x,y,z)"… or "(x), "('x,y)," "(x,y,z)"... or "[(ιx) )(φx) ]" or "[Ry]" or analogous expressions, serve to bracket off a proposition; dots occurring otherwise serve to mark a logical product. The general principle is that a larger number of dots indicates an outside bracket, a smaller number indicates an inside bracket. The exact rule as to the scope of the bracket indicated by dots is arrived at by dividing the occurrences of dots into three groups which we will name I, II, and III. Group I consists of dots adjoining a sign of implication () or of equivalence (≡) or of disjunction (v) or of equality by definition (= Df). Group II consists of dots following brackets indicative of an apparent variable, such as (x) or (x, y) or (x) or (x, y) or [(ιx) )(φx)] or analogous expressions*. Group III consists of dots which stand between propositions in order to indicate a logical product. Group I is of greater force than Group II, and Group II than Group III. The scope of the bracket indicated by any collection of dots extends backwards or forwards beyond any smaller number of dots, or any equal number from a group of less force, until we reach either the end of the asserted proposition or a greater number of dots or an equal number belonging to a group of equal or superior force. Dots indicating a logical product have a scope which works both backwards and forwards; other dots only work away from the adjacent sign of disjunction, implication, or equivalence, or forward from the adjacent symbol of one of the other kinds enumerated in Group II.

Some examples will serve to illustrate the use of dots.

"p v q . . q v p" means the proposition "'p or q' implies 'q or p."' When we assert this proposition, instead of merely considering it, we write

" : p v q . . q v p,"

where the two dots after the assertion-sign show that what is asserted is the whole of what follows the assertion-sign, since there are not as many as two dots anywhere else. If we had written "p: v: q . . q v p," that would mean the proposition "either p is true, or q implies 'q or p."' If we wished to assert this, we should have to put three dots after the assertion-sign. If we had written "p v q . . q : v : p," that would mean the proposition "either ‘p or q’ implies q, or p is true." The forms "p . v . q . . q v p" and "p v q . . q . v . p" have no meaning.

"p q . : q r . . p r" will mean "if p implies q, then if q implies r, p implies r." If we wish to assert this (which is true) we write

" :. p q : q r.”  

Again "p q . . q . r : . p r" will mean "if 'p implies q' implies 'q implies r,' then p implies r." This is in general untrue. (Observe that "p q" is sometimes most conveniently read as "p implies q," and sometimes as "if p, then q.") "p q . q r. . p r " will mean "if p implies q, and q implies r, then p implies r." In this formula, the first dot indicates a logical product; hence the scope of the second dot extends backwards to the beginning of the proposition. " p q: q r . . p r" will mean "p implies q; and if q implies r, then p implies r." (This is not true in general.) Here the two dots indicate a logical product; since two dots do not occur anywhere else, the scope of these two dots extends backwards to the beginning of the proposition, and forwards to the end.

"p v q . :. p . v . q r : . p v r" will mean "if either p or q is true, then if either p or 'q implies r' is true, it follows that either p or r is true." If this is to be asserted, we must put four dots after the assertion-sign, thus:

" :: p v q . ) :. p . v . q r : . p v r."

(This proposition is proved in the body of the work; it is *2.75.) If we wish to assert (what is equivalent to the above) the proposition: "if either p or q is true, and either p or 'q implies r' is true, then either p or r is true," we write "

:. p v q : p v q r : . p v r."

Here the first pair of dots indicates a logical product, while the second pair does not. Thus the scope of the second pair of dots passes over the first pair, and back until we reach the three dots after the assertion-sign. Other uses of dots follow the same principles, and will be explained as they are introduced. In reading a proposition, the dots should be noticed first, as they show its structure. In a proposition containing several signs of implication or equivalence, the one with the greatest number of dots before or after it is the principal one: everything that goes before this one is stated by the proposition to imply or be equivalent to everything that comes after it.

* The meaning of these expressions will be explained later, and examples of the use of dots in connection with them are given in post 12.




Script: Bill Mantlo  Pencils: Sal Buscema  Inks: Joe Sinnott  The LeaderÔ © Respective copyright/trademark holders.



Harold R. (Hal) Foster’s Prince Valiant
© Respective copyright/trademark holders.
 

No comments:

Post a Comment