Harold R. (Hal)
Foster’s Prince Valiant
© Respective
copyright/trademark holders.
|
THE purpose of the present section is to set forth the
first stage of the deduction of pure mathematics from its logical foundations.
This first stage is necessarily concerned with deduction itself, i.e. with the principles by which conclusions
are inferred from premises. If it is our purpose to make all our assumptions
explicit, and to effect the deduction of all our other propositions from these
assumptions, it is obvious that the first assumptions we need are those that
are required to make deduction possible. Symbolic logic is often regarded as
consisting of two coordinate parts, the theory of classes and the theory of
propositions. But from our point of view these two parts are not coordinate;
for in the theory of classes we deduce one proposition from another by means of
principles belonging to the theory of propositions, whereas in the theory of
propositions we nowhere require the theory of classes. Hence, in a deductive
system, the theory of propositions necessarily precedes the theory of classes.
But the subject to be treated in what follows is not quite properly described
as the theory of propositions. It is in fact the theory of how one proposition
can be inferred from another. Now in order that one proposition may be inferred
from another, it is necessary that the two should have that relation which
makes the one a consequence of the other. When a proposition q is a consequence of a proposition p, we say that p implies q. Thus
deduction depends upon the relation of implication, and every deductive system
must contain among its premises as many of the properties of implication as are
necessary to legitimate the ordinary procedure of deduction. In the present
section, certain propositions will be stated as premises, and it will be shown
that they are sufficient for all common forms of inference. It will not be
shown that they are all necessary, and it is possible that the number of them
might be diminished. All that is affirmed concerning the premises is (1) that
they are true, (2) that they are sufficient for the theory of deduction, (3)
that we do not know how to diminish their number. But with regard to (2), there
must always be some element of doubt, since it is hard to be sure that one
never uses some principle unconsciously. The habit of being rigidly guided by
formal symbolic rules is a safeguard against unconscious assumptions; but even
this safeguard is not always adequate.
*1.
PRIMITIVE IDEAS AND PROPOSITIONS.
Since all definitions of terms are effected by means of
other terms, every system of definitions which is not circular must start from
a certain apparatus of undefined terms. It is to some extent optional what
ideas we take as undefined in mathematics; the motives guiding our choice will
be (1) to make the number of undefined ideas as small as possible, (2) as
between two systems in which the number is equal, to choose the one which seems
the simpler and easier. We know no way of proving that such and such a system
of undefined ideas contains as few as will give such and such
results*1. Hence we can only say that such and such ideas are undefined in such and such a system, not that they are indefinable. Following Peano, we shall call the undefined ideas and the undemonstrated propositions primitive ideas and primitive propositions respectively. The primitive ideas are explained by means of descriptions intended to point out to the reader what is meant; but the explanations do not constitute definitions, because they really involve the ideas they explain. In the present number, we shall first enumerate the primitive ideas required in this section; then we shall define implication; and then we shall enunciate the primitive propositions required in this section. Every definition or proposition in the work has a number, for purposes of reference. Following Peano, we use numbers having a decimal as well as an integral part, in order to be able to insert new propositions between any two. A change in the integral part of the number will be used to correspond to a new chapter. Definitions will generally have numbers whose decimal part is less than .1, and will be usually put at the beginning of chapters. In references, the integral parts of the numbers of propositions will be distinguished by being preceded by a star; thus "*1'01" will mean the definition or proposition so numbered, and "1" will mean the chapter in which propositions have numbers whose integral part is 1, i.e. the present chapter. Chapters will generally be called "numbers."
results*1. Hence we can only say that such and such ideas are undefined in such and such a system, not that they are indefinable. Following Peano, we shall call the undefined ideas and the undemonstrated propositions primitive ideas and primitive propositions respectively. The primitive ideas are explained by means of descriptions intended to point out to the reader what is meant; but the explanations do not constitute definitions, because they really involve the ideas they explain. In the present number, we shall first enumerate the primitive ideas required in this section; then we shall define implication; and then we shall enunciate the primitive propositions required in this section. Every definition or proposition in the work has a number, for purposes of reference. Following Peano, we use numbers having a decimal as well as an integral part, in order to be able to insert new propositions between any two. A change in the integral part of the number will be used to correspond to a new chapter. Definitions will generally have numbers whose decimal part is less than .1, and will be usually put at the beginning of chapters. In references, the integral parts of the numbers of propositions will be distinguished by being preceded by a star; thus "*1'01" will mean the definition or proposition so numbered, and "1" will mean the chapter in which propositions have numbers whose integral part is 1, i.e. the present chapter. Chapters will generally be called "numbers."
PRIMITIVE IDEAS.
(1) Elementary
propositions. By an "elementary"
proposition we mean one which does not involve any variables, or, in other
language, one which does not involve such words as "all,"
"some," "the" or equivalents for such words. A proposition
such as "this is red," where "this" is something given in
sensation, will be elementary. Any combination of given elementary propositions
by means of negation, disjunction or conjunction (see below) will be
elementary. In the primitive propositions of the present number, and therefore
in the deductions from these primitive propositions in *2-*5,
the letters p, q, r, s will be used to denote elementary
propositions.
(2) Elementary
propositional functions. By an "elementary propositional
function" we shall mean an expression containing an undetermined constituent,
i.e. a variable, or several such
constituents, and such that, when the undetermined constituent or constituents
are determined, i.e. when values are
assigned to the variable or variables, the resulting value of the expression in
question is an elementary proposition. Thus if p is an undetermined elementary proposition, "not-p" is
an elementary propositional function.
We shall show in *9
how to extend the results of this and the following numbers (*1-*5) to propositions which are not elementary.
(3) Assertion.
Any proposition may be either asserted or merely considered. If I say "Caesar died," I assert the
proposition "Caesar died," if
I say "'Caesar died' is a proposition," I make a different assertion,
and "Caesar died" is no longer asserted, but merely considered.
Similarly in a hypothetical proposition, e.g.
"if a = b, then b = a," we have two un-asserted
propositions, namely "a = b" and "b = a," while what
is asserted is that the first of these implies the second. In language, we
indicate when a proposition is merely considered by "if so-and-so" or
"that so-and-so" or merely by inverted commas. In symbols, if p is a proposition, p by itself will
stand for the un-asserted proposition, while the asserted proposition will be
designated by
"┣ . p."
The sign "┣
" is called the assertion-sign*2; it may be read "it is true that"
(although philosophically this is not exactly what it means). The dots after
the assertion-sign indicate its range; that is to say, everything following is
asserted until we reach either an equal number of dots preceding a sign of
implication or the end of the sentence. Thus "┣ :
p . ⊃ ┣ .
q" means " it is true that p implies q," whereas "┣ .
p . ⊃ ┣ .
q" means "p is true; therefore q is true." The first of these does
not necessarily involve the truth either of p
or of q, while the second involves
the truth of both.
(4) Assertion of
a propositional function. Besides the assertion of definite propositions,
we need what we shall call "assertion of a propositional function."
The general notion of asserting any
propositional function is not used until *9,
but we use at once the notion of asserting various special elementary
propositional functions. Let φx be a
propositional function whose argument is x;
then we may assert φx without
assigning a value to x. This is done,
for example, when the law of identity is asserted in the form " A is A."
Here A is left undetermined, because,
however A may be determined, the
result will be true. Thus when we assert φx, leaving x undetermined, we are asserting an ambiguous value of our
function. This is only legitimate if, however the ambiguity may be determined,
the result will be true. Thus take, as an illustration, the primitive
proposition *1.2 below,
namely
"┣ : p v
p . ⊃ .
p,"
i.e.
"'p or p' implies p." Here p may be any elementary proposition: by
leaving p undetermined, we obtain an assertion which can be applied to any
particular elementary proposition. Such assertions are like the particular
enunciations in Euclid: when it is said "let ABC be an isosceles triangle; then the angles at the base will be
equal," what is said applies to any isosceles triangle; it is stated
concerning one triangle, but not concerning a definite one. All the assertions
in the present work, with a very few exceptions, assert propositional
functions, not definite propositions.
As a matter of fact, no constant elementary proposition
will occur in the present work, or can occur in any work which employs only
logical ideas. The ideas and propositions of logic are all general: an assertion (for example) which is
true of Socrates but not of Plato, will not belong to logic*3, and if an assertion which is true of both is to occur in logic, it must not be made concerning either, but concerning a variable x. In order to obtain, in logic, a definite proposition instead of a propositional function, it is necessary to take some propositional function and assert that it is true always or sometimes, i.e. with all possible values of the variable or with some possible value. Thus, giving the name "individual" to whatever there is that is neither a proposition nor a function, the proposition "every individual is identical with itself" or the proposition "there are individuals" will be a proposition belonging to logic. But these propositions are not elementary.
true of Socrates but not of Plato, will not belong to logic*3, and if an assertion which is true of both is to occur in logic, it must not be made concerning either, but concerning a variable x. In order to obtain, in logic, a definite proposition instead of a propositional function, it is necessary to take some propositional function and assert that it is true always or sometimes, i.e. with all possible values of the variable or with some possible value. Thus, giving the name "individual" to whatever there is that is neither a proposition nor a function, the proposition "every individual is identical with itself" or the proposition "there are individuals" will be a proposition belonging to logic. But these propositions are not elementary.
(5) Negation.
If p is any proposition, the
proposition "not-p," or
"p is false," will be
represented by "~p." For
the present, p must be an elementary proposition.
(6) Disjunction.
If p and q are any propositions, the proposition "p or q," i.e. "either p is true or q is
true," where the alternatives are to be not mutually exclusive, will be
represented by
"p v q."
This is called the disjunction or the logical sum of p and q. Thus "~ p v q"
will mean "p is false or q is true"; ~(p v q) will mean "it is false that either p or q is true,"
which is equivalent to "p and q are both false"; “~(p v
~q) will mean "it is false that
either p is false or q is false," which is equivalent to
"p and q are both true "; and so on. For the present, p and q must be elementary
propositions.
The above are all the primitive ideas required in the
theory of deduction. Other primitive ideas will be introduced in Section B.
Definition
of Implication. When a proposition q follows from a proposition p,
so that if p is true, q must also be true, we say that p implies q. The idea of implication, in the form in which we require it, can
be defined. The meaning to be given to implication in what follows may at first
sight appear somewhat artificial; but although there are other legitimate
meanings, the one here adopted is very much more convenient for our purposes
than any of its rivals. The essential property that we require of implication
is this: "What is implied by a true proposition is true." It is in
virtue of this property that implication yields proofs. But this property by no
means determines whether anything, and if so what, is implied by a false
proposition. What it does determine is that, if p implies q, then it cannot be
the case that p is true and q is false, i.e. it must be the case that either p
is false or q is true. The most convenient interpretation of implication is to
say, conversely, that if either p is
false or q is true, then "p implies q" is to be true. Hence "p implies q" is to
be defined to mean: "Either p is
false or q is true." Hence we
put:
*1.01. p ⊃ q
. = . ~p v q Df.
Here the letters "Df" stand for "definition." They and the sign of
equality together are to be regarded as forming one
symbol, standing for " is defined to mean*4." Whatever comes to the left of the sign of equality is defined to mean the same as what comes to the right of it. Definition is not among the primitive ideas, because definitions are concerned solely with the symbolism, not with what is symbolized; they are introduced for practical convenience, and are theoretically unnecessary.
symbol, standing for " is defined to mean*4." Whatever comes to the left of the sign of equality is defined to mean the same as what comes to the right of it. Definition is not among the primitive ideas, because definitions are concerned solely with the symbolism, not with what is symbolized; they are introduced for practical convenience, and are theoretically unnecessary.
In virtue of the above definition, when "p ⊃ q" holds, then either p is false or q is true; hence if p is
true, q must be true. Thus the above
definition preserves the essential characteristic of implication; it gives, in
fact, the most general meaning compatible with the preservation of this
characteristic.
*1
The recognized methods of proving independence are not applicable, without
reserve, to fundamentals. Cf. Principles of Mathematics, ~ 17. What is there
said concerning primitive propositions applies with even greater force to
primitive ideas.
*2
We have adopted both the idea and the symbol of assertion from Frege. t Cf.
Principles of Mathematics, ~ 38.
*3
When we say that a proposition "belongs to logic," we mean that it
can be expressed in terms of the primitive ideas of logic. We do not mean that
logic applies to it, for that would of course be true of any proposition.
*4
The sign of equality not followed by the letters "Df" will have a
different meaning, to be defined later.
Artist Unknown (tribe unknown) mask © Respective copyright holders |
Pencils: Jack Kirby Inks: Mike Royer
TM © Respective copyright/trademark
holders. |
Here our authors are laying the foundation of our logical
system. Although this is all covered thoroughly in the introduction, they begin
again taking baby steps, but using expanded, and language I find more accessible.
The aspect of this language that appeals to me so much is the seeming repetition
of thought expressed for ever greater degrees of fine distinctions. The text is
a recipe for a specific line of symbolic rules we may use to go forward in
reasoning undistracted by subconscious reasoning that may lead to error.
TM © Respective copyright/trademark
holders
|
Script: Elliot Maggin Artwork: Kurt Schaffenberger
TM © Respective copyright/trademark
holders. |
Harold R. (Hal)
Foster’s Prince Valiant © Respective
copyright/trademark holders.
|
No comments:
Post a Comment