Harold R. (Hal)
Foster’s Prince Valiant
© Respective
copyright/trademark holders.
Both classes and relations have properties analogous to
most of those of propositions that result from negation and the logical sum.
The logical product of two classes a
and b is their common part, i.e. the class of terms which are members of both. This is
represented by a Ç b.
Thus we put
a Ç b =
x^(x є a . x є b) Df.
This gives us
├ : x є a Ç b . º . x є a . x є b,
├ : x є a Ç b . º . x є a . x є b,
i.e. "x is a member of the logical
product of a and b"
is equivalent to the logical product of "x is a member of a"
and "x is a member of b."
Similarly the logical
sum of two classes a and b
is the class of terms which are members of either; we denote it by a È b.
The definition is
a È b =
x^(x є a . v
. x є b) Df,
and the connection with the logical sum of propositions
is given by
├ :.
x є a È b .
º : x є a .
v . x є b.
The negation
of a class a consists of those terms x
for which " x є a " can be
significantly and truly denied. We shall find that there are terms of other
types for which "x є a"
is neither true nor false, but nonsense. These terms are not members of the
negation of a.
Thus the negation of a class a
is the class of terms of suitable type which are not members of it, i.e. the class x^(x ~ є a).
We call this class "—a" (read "not-a"); thus the definition
is
--a = x^(x ~є a) Df,
and the connection with the negation of propositions is
given by
├ :
x є --a . º .
x ~є a.
In place of
implication we have the relation of inclusion.
A class a is said to be included or contained in a
class b if all members of a
are members of b, i.e. if x є a Éx .
x є b. We write a Ì b"
for "a is contained in b."
Thus we put
a Ì b .
=:x є a . É. x
є b Df.
Most of the formulae concerning ‘p . q,’ ‘p v q,’ ‘~p,’ ‘p É q’
remain true if we substitute ‘a Ç b,’
‘a È b,’
‘--a,’ ‘a Ì b.’
In place of equivalence, we substitute identity; for ‘p º q’
was defined as ‘p É q
. q É p,’ but ‘a Ì b .
b Ì a’
gives
‘x є a . º . x є b,’ whence ‘a = b.’
gives
‘x є a . º . x є b,’ whence ‘a = b.’
Script: Stan Lee Pencils Pencils: Jack Kirby Inks: Vince
Colletta The Mighty ThorÔ ©
Respective copyright/trademark holders.
In considering two strings of ponies ‘p and q,’ ‘p’ having two Pintos and six palominos; and ‘q’ having four Pintos, two Palominos and three Appaloosas.
Additionally the p string includes
two stallions and six mares while the q
string is made of three stallions and six mares.
The class of ponies considered at hand
is named: a; ø represents the category Pintos; y represents the category Palaminos; χ represents the category Appaloosas; each
pony is an individual, having specific variable characteristics (x1 (stallion) , x2
(mare) , x3,
…). The above class may be expressed
a Î p { φ(x1, x2) . ψ
( x1 . x2 )} . V . q { φ(x1, x2)
. ψ(x1 . x2) .χ(x1 . x2)}
p ∩ q = x^(φx1 . φx2 . ψx2 -3)
p ∪ q = x^(φx1 . φx2 . ψ . ψx2 . χ1 . χ2)
This example is really only illustrative of the system, and seems sort of shooting a mosquito with an elephant gun, but I intend that it show the utility of thinking in terms of propositional equations. One could continue listing any number of additional x variables describing the individual animals for any purpose desired, and we can see that this allows comparisons and perhaps exclusions much more accurately and concisely than is possible using language alone.
John Wayne Adventure Comics Pencils: Frank Frazetta Inks: Al Williamson © Respective copyright/trademark holders.
Harold R. (Hal)
Foster’s Prince Valiant
© Respective
copyright/trademark holders.
No comments:
Post a Comment