Friday, October 5, 2012

22. Specific Aspects of Constructing and Using Symbols

Harold R. (Hal) Foster’s Prince Valiant
© Respective copyright/trademark holders

Every use of "(ɿx)(φx),” where it apparently occurs as a constituent of a proposition in the place of an object, is defined in terms of the primitive ideas already on hand. An example of this definition in use is given by the proposition "E ! (ɿx)(φx)" which is considered immediately. The whole subject is treated more fully ahead in Chapter III.

The symbol should be compared and contrasted with "x^x)" which in use can always be read as "the x's which satisfy φx." Both symbols are incomplete symbols defined only in use, and as such are discussed in Chapter III. The symbol " x^x)" always has an application, namely to the class determined by φx; but "(ɿx)(φx)" only has an application when φx^ is only satisfied by one value of x, neither more nor less. It should also be observed that the meaning given to the symbol by the definition, given immediately below, of E ! (ɿx)(φx). does not presuppose that we know the meaning of "one." This is also characteristic of the definition of any other use of (ɿx)(φx).

  

We now proceed to define "E! (ɿx)(φx)” so that it can be read "the x satisfying φx exists." (It will be observed that this is a different meaning of existence from that which we express by “.") Its definition is

    E ! ((ɿx) (φx) . = :  (c) : φx . ºx . x =c  Df,

i.e. "the x satisfying φx^ exists" is to mean "there is an object c such that φx is true when x is c but not otherwise."

The following are equivalent forms:

    ┠ :. E! (ɿx) (φx) . º : (c) : φc : φx. É . x = c,

    ┠ :. E! (ɿx) (φx) . º : (c) . φc : φx φy Éxy .    x = y,

    ┠ :. E! (ɿx) (φx) . º : (c) : φc : x c . Éx .     ~ φx.

The last of these states that "the x satisfying φ^ exists" is equivalent to "there is an object c satisfying φ^, and every object other than c does not satisfy φ^."

The kind of existence just defined covers a great many cases. Thus for example "the most perfect Being exists" will mean:

    (c) : x is most perfect. . ºx . x = c,

which, taking the last of the above equivalences, is equivalent to

 (c): c is most perfect : x ≠ c . Éx . x is not most perfect.

A proposition such as "Apollo exists" is really of the same logical form, although it does not explicitly contain the word the. For "Apollo" means really "the object having such-and-such properties," say "the object having the properties enumerated in the Classical Dictionary*. "If these properties make up the propositional function φx, then "Apollo" means "(ɿx)(φx)," and "Apollo exists" means "E! "(ɿx)(φx)." To take another illustration, "the author of Waverley" means "the man who (or rather, the object which) wrote Waverley." Thus "Scott is the author of Waverley" is

    Scott = (ɿx)(x wrote Waverley).   

Here (as we observed before) the importance of identity in connection with descriptions plainly appears.

The notation “(ɿx) (φx),” which is long and inconvenient, is seldom used, being chiefly required to lead up to another notation, namely "Rʻy," meaning "the object having the relation R to y." That is, we put

    Rʻy = (ɿx) (xRy)  Df.

The inverted comma may be read "of." Thus "Rʻy" is read "the R of y." Thus if R is the relation of father to son, " Rʻy" means "the father of y"; if R is the relation of son to father, "Rʻy" means "the son of y," which will only "exist" if y has one son and no more. R'y is a function of y, but not a propositional function; we shall call it a descriptive function. All the ordinary functions of mathematics are of this kind, as will appear more fully in the sequel. Thus in our notation, " sin y" would be written " sin ʻy," and "sin" would stand for the relation which sin ʻy has to y. Instead of a variable descriptive function ƒy, we put Rʻy, where the variable relation R takes the place of the variable function ƒ. A descriptive function will in general exist while y belongs to a certain domain, but not outside that domain; thus if we are dealing with positive rationals, y will be significant if y is a perfect square, but not otherwise; if we are dealing with real numbers, and agree that "y" is to mean the positive square root (or, is to mean the negative square root), √y will be significant provided y is positive, but not otherwise; and so on.

Thus every descriptive function has what we may call a "domain of definition" or a "domain of existence," which may be thus defined: If the function in question is Rʻy, its domain of definition or of existence will be the class of those arguments y for which we have E! Rʻy, i.e. for which E!(ɿx)(xRy), i.e. for which there is one x, and no more, having the relation R to y.

If R is any relation, we will speak of Rʻy as the "associated descriptive function." A great many of the constant relations which we shall have occasion to introduce are only or chiefly important on account of their associated descriptive functions. In such cases, it is easier (though less correct) to begin by assigning the meaning of the descriptive function, and to deduce the meaning of the relation from that of the descriptive function. This will be explored in the explanations of notation in the next post.

* The same principle applies to many uses of the proper names of existent objects, e.g. to all uses of proper names for objects known to the speaker only by report, and not by personal acquaintance (i.e. the Holy Grail, the North Pole, the elephants graveyard).

Script: Richard Hughes  Pencils and inks: Chic Stone
© Respective copyright/trademark holders.

The above part begins to address the process of constructing symbols that can serve to represent thoughts, expressions, objects, relations, etc. with which we may construct our propositional equations. Aspects of this system appear akin to binary language in nature. In fact we will, in future posts examine the construction of similar even more compact equations by means of ‘the stroke,’ that are again a step towards even more simplification. Clearly this system may be translated into binary code and function on a computer in some fashion; but it would have no useful function. The purpose of this system is to bring order to thought, improve the processing of stored data of the mind and integrate it with new perceptions, in real time. This is accomplished by understanding the nature of this data and systems of combining it in increasingly more efficient ways, with avoiding error as the main priority.

With regard to my thoughts in the last previous post here, on Evident Reality as a logical tool to add equational ‘proof’ to Einstein’s Theories of Special and General Relativity, applying physical and cultural data derived from our shared and collected human experience; by means of Whitehead and Russell’s system of logical philosophy. Below is an initial framing of the equation I laid out this afternoon over three cups of coffee, using mainly elements we have already encountered in previous posts. As we see below, with our system, great complexity begins with a relatively simple set of divisions in which great complexity may be divined.
I summed my scribbling up for my waiter with the quote at the top of the sheet paraphrasing the authors: ‘analysis applied to process equals division. ’

An example of this blogger’s regrettable handwriting.
Scripted (perhaps by): Al Capp  Pencils and Inks: Frank Frazetta  © Respective copyright/trademark holders.
 
 
Harold R. (Hal) Foster’s Prince Valiant
© Respective copyright/trademark holders
 

No comments:

Post a Comment