Harold R. (Hal)
Foster’s Prince Valiant
© Respective
copyright/trademark holders.
|
Possible arguments for functions
When it is said that e.g. "φ(φz^)" is
meaningless, and therefore neither true nor false, it is necessary to avoid a
misunderstanding. If “φ(φz^)" were
interpreted as meaning "the value for φz^
with the argument φz^ is
true," that would be not meaningless, but false. It is false for the same
reason for which "the King of France is bald" is false, namely
because there is no such thing as "the value for φz^ with the argument
φz^." But when,
with some argument a, we assert φa we are not meaning
to assert "the value for φx^
with the argument a is true"; we
are meaning to assert the actual proposition which is the value for φx^ with the argument
a. Thus for example if φx^ is "x^ is a
man," φ(Socrates) will be "Socrates is a man,”
not "the value for the function ‘x^
is a man,' with the argument Socrates, is true." Thus in accordance with
our principle that "φ(φz^)" is meaningless, we
cannot legitimately deny "the function 'x is a man' is a man,"
because this is nonsense, but we can legitimately
deny " the value for the function 'x^ is a man' with the argument 'x^ is a
man' is true," not on the ground that the value in question is false, but
on the ground that there is no such value for the function.
We will denote by the symbol "(x). φx" the
proposition " φx
always*," i.e. the proposition
which asserts all the values for φx^.
This proposition involves the function φx^,
not merely an ambiguous value of the function. The assertion of φx, where x is unspecified, is a different
assertion from the one which asserts all values for φx^ for the former is
an ambiguous assertion, whereas the latter is in no sense ambiguous. It will be
observed that "(x) . φx"
does not assert "φx with all values of
x," because, as we have seen,
there must be values of x with which "φx " is meaningless.
What is asserted by "(x) . φx" is all
propositions which are values for φx^;
hence it is only with such values of x
as make "φx"
significant, i.e. with all possible arguments, that φx is asserted when
we assert "(x) . φx." Thus a
convenient way to read "(x) . φx" is "φx is true with all possible values of x." This is, however, a less
accurate reading than " φx
always," because the notion of truth
is not part of the content of what is judged. When we judge "all men are
mortal," we judge truly, but the notion of truth is not necessarily in our
minds, any more than it need be when we judge "Socrates is mortal."
*
We use "always" as meaning "in all cases," not "at all
times." Similarly "sometimes"
will mean "in some cases."
'Wringle Wrangle" - Pencils and Inks: Jesse Marsh © Respective copyright/trademark holders. |
Studying Principia Mathematica is as a path to ambiguity. The
system that we may learn is individual, and I infer it to be of various use to
each who attempts to learn it. It is rater unique because the authors Alfred
North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell saw that the system was a vehicle rather
than a destination, and that some readers would be defeated, some readers would
be right with them, and some readers would continue on with modifications they
hadn’t anticipated. Each of the posts up to here, and also those to come, are
layers of fine distinction in both thought (perception) and expression, by
whatever form it takes. There are aspects, such as the vicious-circle
principle, that are challenging to conscious perception. I have experienced
great feelings of joy and amusement in reading and re-reading various passages
of this text, delighted at the amazing crazy fine distinctions beyond anything
I expected.
The nature of taking in our
system cannot be subject to conscious recitation, instead a better gauge is to
turn back and read the posts again, and when you find that you can breeze thru
them easily and understand them as you do a comic strip that is the key to this
bus. There
are two aspects at play in our text, ‘the system of symbols and their form in
use’ and ‘the fine distinctions that are the reasons for the necessity of the
system.’ The forms allow the construction of any sort of propositions,
functions, objects, classes and more in a form that immediately (visually)
reveals any errors within the structure. This is only possible by the
systematic application of this metaphysical system.Pencils and Inks: Ken Bald © Respective copyright holder. |
Harold R. (Hal)
Foster’s Prince Valiant
© Respective
copyright/trademark holders.
|
No comments:
Post a Comment