<
It is clear that our system prevents contradictions by understanding how they may arise and steering clear. As we have seen above in the authors’ treatment of four classic mathematical contradictions, their resolution presented is not the result of any external changes in the problems themselves; but solely in our perception of the problems in terms of our system. Nearly all insolvable problems can find a resolution with a new approach, a fresh look or a change in attitude.
Harold R. (Hal)
Foster’s Prince Valiant
© Respective
copyright/trademark holders.
|
VIII. The Contradictions (for example).
We are now in a position to show how the theory of
types affects the solution of the contradictions which have beset mathematical
logic. For this purpose, we shall begin by an enumeration of some of the more
important and illustrative of these contradictions, and shall then show how
they all embody vicious-circle fallacies, and are therefore all avoided by the
theory of types. It will be noticed that these paradoxes do not relate
exclusively to the ideas of number and quantity. Accordingly no solution can be
adequate which seeks to explain them merely as the result of some illegitimate
use of these ideas. The solution must be sought in some such scrutiny of
fundamental logical ideas as has been attempted in the foregoing pages.
(1) The oldest contradiction of the kind in question is
the Epimenides. Epimenides the Cretan
said that all Cretans were liars, and all other statements made by Cretans were
certainly lies. Was this a lie? The simplest form of this contradiction is
afforded by the man who says "I am lying"; if he is lying, he is
speaking the truth, and vice versa.
<<(1) When a man says "I am lying," we
may interpret his statement as: "There is a proposition which I am
affirming and which is false." That is to say, he is asserting the truth
of some value of the function "I assert p, and p is false."
But we saw that the word " false " is ambiguous, and that, in order
to make it unambiguous, we must specify the order of falsehood, or, what comes
to the same thing, the order of the proposition to which falsehood is ascribed.
We saw also that, if p is a
proposition of the nth order, a proposition in which p occurs as an apparent variable is not of the nth order, but of a higher order. Hence the kind of truth or
falsehood which can belong to the statement "there is a proposition p which I am affirming and which has
falsehood of the nth order" is
truth or falsehood of a higher order than the nth. Hence the statement of Epimenides does not fall within its own
scope, and therefore no contradiction emerges. If we regard the statement
"I am lying" as a compact way of simultaneously making all the
following statements: "I am asserting a false proposition of the first
order," "I am asserting a false proposition of the second
order," and so on, we find the following curious state of things: As no
proposition of the first order is being asserted, the statement "I am
asserting a false proposition of the first order" is false. This statement
is of the second order, hence the statement "I am making a false statement
of the second order" is true. This is a statement of the third order, and
is the only statement of the third order which is being made. Hence the
statement "I am making a false statement of the third order" is
false. Thus we see that the statement "I am making a false statement of
order 2n + 1" is false, while the statement "I am making a false
statement of order 2n" is true.
But in this state of things there is no contradiction.
(2) Let w be the class of all those classes which are
not members of themselves. Then, whatever class x may be, "x is a w" is equivalent to "x is not an x." Hence, giving to x
the value w, "w is a w" is equivalent to "w
is not a w."
<<(2) In order to solve the contradiction about
the class of classes which are not members of themselves, we shall assume, what
will be explained in the next Chapter, that a proposition about a class is
always to be reduced to a statement about
a function which defines the class, i.e.
about a function which is satisfied by the members of the class and by no other
arguments. Thus a class is an object
derived from a function and presupposing the function, just as, for example, (x). φx
presupposes the function φx^.
Hence a class cannot, by the vicious-circle principle, significantly be the
argument to its defining function, that is to say, if we denote by “z^(φz)"
the class defined by φz^,
the symbol "φ{z^(φz)}"
must be meaningless. Hence a class neither satisfies nor does not satisfy its
defining function, and therefore (as will appear more fully in Chapter III) is
neither a member of itself nor not a member of itself. This is an immediate
consequence of the limitation to the possible arguments to a function which was
explained at the beginning of the present Chapter. Thus if a
is a class, the statement "a
is not a member of a" is always
meaningless, and there is therefore no sense in the phrase "the class of
those classes which are not members of themselves." Hence the
contradiction which results from supposing that there is such a class
disappears.
(3) Let T be
the relation that subsists between two relations R and S whenever R does not have the relation R to S.
Then, whatever relations R and S may be, "R has the relation T to S" is equivalent to "R does not have the relation R to
S." Hence, giving the value T to
both R and S, "T has the
relation T to T" is equivalent to "T
does not have the relation T to T."
<<(3) Exactly similar remarks apply to "the
relation which holds between R and S whenever R does not have the relation R
to i." Suppose the relation R is
defined by a function φ(x, y), i.e. R holds between x and y whenever φ(x, y) is true, but not otherwise. Then
in order to interpret "R has the
relation R to S," we shall have to suppose that R and S can significantly
be the arguments to φ. But (assuming, as will
appear in Chapter III, that R
presupposes its defining function) this would require that φ
should be able to take as argument an object which is defined in terms of φ,
and this no function can do, as we saw at the beginning of this Chapter. Hence
"R has the relation R to S"
is meaningless, and the contradiction ceases.
(4) Burali-Forti's contradiction may be stated as
follows: It can be shown that every well-ordered series has an ordinal number,
that the series of ordinals up to and including any given ordinal exceeds the
given ordinal by one, and (on certain very natural assumptions) that the series
of all ordinals (in order of magnitude) is well-ordered. It follows that the
series of all ordinals has an ordinal number, Ω say. But in that case the
series of all ordinals including Ω has the ordinal number Ω + 1, which must be greater than Ω. Hence Ω
is not the ordinal number of all ordinals.
<<(4) The solution of Burali-Forti's
contradiction requires some further developments for its solution. At this
stage, it must suffice to observe that a series is a relation, and an ordinal
number is a class of series. (These statements are justified in the body of the
work.) Hence a series of ordinal numbers is a relation between classes of
relations, and is of higher type than any of the series which are members of
the ordinal numbers in question. Burali-Forti's "ordinal number of all
ordinals" must be the ordinal number of all ordinals of a given type, and
must therefore be of higher type than any of these ordinals. Hence it is not
one of these ordinals, and there is no contradiction in its being greater than
any of them.
Pencils and Inks: George Evans © Respective copyright/trademark holders.
|
It is clear that our system prevents contradictions by understanding how they may arise and steering clear. As we have seen above in the authors’ treatment of four classic mathematical contradictions, their resolution presented is not the result of any external changes in the problems themselves; but solely in our perception of the problems in terms of our system. Nearly all insolvable problems can find a resolution with a new approach, a fresh look or a change in attitude.
Dan DeCarlo The
greatest of all time comic book artist!
Archie Andrews
Gang © Respective copyright/trademark
holders.
|
Harold R. (Hal)
Foster’s Prince Valiant
© Respective
copyright/trademark holders.
|
No comments:
Post a Comment